H-NET BOOK REVIEW
Published by H-SHEAR@h-net.msu.edu (February, 2000)
Amy Dru Stanley. _From Bondage to Contract: Wage Labor, Marriage
and the Market in the Era of Slave Emanipation_. Index,
Bibliography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. $59.95
(cloth), ISBN 0-521-41470-9; $18.95 (paper), 0-521-63526-8.
Reviewed for H-SHEAR by Daniel Hamilton ,
Harvard University
In his 1909 article on "Liberty of Contract" in the Yale Law
Journal, Roscoe Pound argued that an emerging judicial notion of
freedom of contract which assumed equal bargaining power between the
parties was "a fallacy to everyone acquainted at first hand with
industrial conditions." Pound asked "why then do courts persist in
the fallacy? Why do so many of them force upon legislation an
academic theory of equality in the face of practical conditions of
inequality." Pound argued that this approach was due to "an
individualist conception of justice, which exaggerates the
importance of property and of -- contract [and] exaggerates private
right at the expense of public right..." For some legal historians,
most particularly and most importantly Morton Horwitz, Pound's
article other more technical challenges to existing contract
doctrines that emerged in that era, represented a watershed point in
the history of contract. In this analysis, Pound, anticipating
Legal Realism, mounted an "internal critique of late-19th century
contract doctrine that initially undermined the foundations of
Classical Legal Thought."[1]
Amy Dru Stanley tells a different story and a highly persuasive one.
In her important new book she finds that the first sustained
critique of the foundations of classical laissez-faire conceptions
of contract began not with Pound and later the Realists, but instead
in the aftermath of the Civil War. As she tells it, abolitionists
were able during the war to use free market contract ideology to
undermine chattel slavery. After the war a society that had argued
over the meaning of slavery and emancipation "drew on contract to
describe the changes in their world and to distinguish between the
commodity relations of freedom and bondage." (ix) Stanley find that
in the postbellum era different groups, most particularly freed
slaves, Yankee hirelings, and married women each questioned "the
moral boundaries of market relations," and used the problem of
contact as a way to "reconsider the meaning of freedom." (xi) She
finds that a free market ideal of contract based on voluntary
exchange by individuals who were formally equal and free came under
searing scrutiny and criticism in the 1870s and 1880s. This ideal,
which "defined commerce in free labor as emancipation" competed
with alternative radical ideals advanced by industrial wage-workers
that "in selling their labor they were no more self-owning than
slaves." (xiii) Stanley has exhaustively mined postbellum debate
over contract and shows us that the twentieth century challenge to
the professed neutrality and equality of contract doctrine was built
upon an important historical tradition.
Stanley's book, however, is significant not only for the way it
provides antecedents to the Realists and complicates the
periodization of critiques of contract doctrine. In her view,
antislavery forces, by connecting ideas of contract with ideas of
freedom, set in motion a fundamental debate over the proper role of
the market and political economy -- debate that was framed
explicitly in contract terms. Stanley looks at the way freedmen and
freedwomen, wage laborers, and married women each took up contract
ideology and shaped it to quite different and fascinating ends.
Once slavery was assaulted on contract grounds, other groups had a
powerful weapon with which to challenge the more coercive elements
of nineteenth century liberalism.
Diverse actors seized upon this weapon after the Civil War to reveal
the contradictions of coercion and legal dependence that still
existed in the face of professed free labor. Methods and strategies
and goals differed from group to group, but taken as a whole, their
critiques and analysis forced a fundamental reconsideration of
political economy, wage labor, home life and ultimately of the
definition of self-ownership and the meaning of freedom. Stanley's
analysis is elegant, ambitious and powerful, and helps provide a new
understanding of the ideological consequences of emancipation.
From Bondage to Contract is a major contribution to nineteenth
century legal history and should become a necessary companion to the
work of Eric Foner as an analysis of the central role of labor
ideology and the shifting contours of liberalism in the Civil War
era.
The book is divided into five chapters that proceed thematically
rather than chronologically. She begins with a theoretical
exploration of the ideal of contract freedom in the postbellum
period. Here Maine's famous maxim that progressive societies move
"from status to contract" is contextualized and Americanized by
Stanley. Drawing on the work of William Graham Sumner, James Kent,
Theophilus Parson and dozens of their contemporaries, Stanley
explores the way American legal theorists took Blackstone and Smith,
Hobbes and Locke and applied them in the 1860s and 1870s to
America's labor market and American households.
Beginning with extensive discussion ofLeviathan, The Second
Treatise of Government, The Wealth of Nations, and Blackstone's
Commentaries, we move by chapter's end from seventeenth and
eighteenth century England to post-Civil War America.
Methodologically this is a striking and also subtle achievement --
the transition from high intellectual history to an on-the-ground
application of political theory is seamless and effective. Drawing
on Enlightenment thinkers, Stanley shows how contract, in postbellum
America, "reconciled human autonomy and obligation, imposing social
order through personal volition rather than external force." (2)
Contract thus was "premised on self-ownership," and parties "had to
be sovereigns of themselves, possessive individuals entitled to
their own persons, labors and faculties." (3) At the same time the
postbellum view of contract as synonymous with personal autonomy was
explicitly gendered, and led to an "asymmetry between rules of
voluntary exchange that assumed equality in the marketplace and that
assured subordination in the household." (17) This asymmetry
between equality and subordination in the free market at home is the
focal point of Stanley's book and it is this tension that drives her
narrative.
There are two distinct stages to this narrative, one pre-war and one
post-war. The first part is dominated by the abolitionists, who
seized upon the debate over emancipation to bring discussion of
ideals of contract freedom to the fore. For Stanley "the conflict
over slavery infused the principles of self-ownership, consent and
exchange with new ideological urgency." (17) It was the inability
to enter into contract -- to be forced into obligation without
consent or exchange -- that best defined slavery for abolitionists.
This line of argument led to the conclusion that a voluntary
contract obligation to sell one's labor was by definition synonymous
with freedom -- a point of view patently at odds with notions of
wage slavery and one that would draw fire from hirelings after the
war. For antislavery forces, however, "legitimizing wage labor was
a central part of the abolitionist project" (21) and activists had
"reshaped the meaning of contract freedom by dissociating wage labor
from relations of personal dependency." (18) For the abolitionists
a right of property in the self, represented by the sale of one's
labor, was the essence of contract freedom, and of freedom
generally.
The abolitionist embrace of contract was not solely an elaboration
of abstract natural rights, but focused also on contracts inside the
family, particularly the marriage contract. Abolitionists succeeded
in "placing the contract between husband and wife at the forefront
of the debate over slavery and freedom." (18) The right to
self-ownership was quite literally embodied by the capacity to enter
into a voluntary marriage contract. Slavery, in taking away control
over one's body, represented the denial of self-ownership symbolized
by the inability to enter into formal, legally enforceable
marriages. In particular abolitionists focused on the abuse
suffered by slave women as evidence that slavery denied this most
basic form of self-ownership. Female slaves "served as the symbol
of the dispossessed self." (27) "Dishonored, stripped bare, the
bondswoman literally embodied the denial of property in the self."
(27)
In arguing that slavery denied female self-ownership of their
bodies, and in defining freedom "through the negative of the female
slave's subjection," abolitionists had unwittingly "opened to
question the right of women to own themselves." (28) This
innovation "held the potential to challenge the categories of sex
difference embedded in classical liberalism and Victorian scientific
theory." (28) This challenge to gender catergories was, Stanley
reminds us, an unintended outcome for a majority of abolitionists,
who for the most part reasserted the validity of distinctions based
on sex. For Stanley, "the dominant abolitionist position was that
slave emancipation would convert freedmen into sovereign,
self-owning individuals," and "property in women would simply be
converted from slaveholders to husbands." (29)
Stanley finds that the inconsistency of this position was fiercely
challenged by black women writers, most particularly by Ellen
Watkins Harper. Taking up the logic of the abolitionist position,
Harper argued in the late 1850s before the American Antislavery
Society and elsewhere that the "husband's claim to property in his
wife violated inalienable rights much as did the slave master's
claim to his chattel property." (31) Stanley examines Harper's
arguments, along with those of Harriet Jacobs and Sarah Parker
Redmond, and concludes that among abolitionists "it was black women
who most unequivocally asserted a women's right to herself" (33) and
"transformed the meaning of contract freedom" by demanding
self-ownership within the marriage contract itself.(34)
In exposing this fissure in the abolitionist movement, Stanley
begins the second part of her narrative. After the War the
abolitionist faith in free wage labor and the rights of marriage was
subject to contestation and critique as different groups and
constituencies advanced alternative visions of contract. With the
onset of emancipation the abolitionist vision was initially put into
action, as "the North began the project of establishing voluntary
wage labor on southern soil and guaranteeing the marriage rights of
former slaves."(35) Stanley vividly describes how agents from the
Freedmen's Bureau sought to put the abolitionist program into place
by introducing a system of labor contracts and attempting to bind
freed slaves into legally recognized marriages. No sooner was this
program undertaken, however, when it met with ideological resistance
from those who felt coerced by the new contract regime, not
liberated. Simply put, perhaps too simply put, once the contract
genie was out of the bottle it could alight on different actors
interested in expanding notions of freedom and self after the Civil
War. New ideas of contract and freedom were articulated to
challenge the connection of freedom with wage labor contracts and
marriage. It is the exploration of these alternative visions of
contract freedom, and their critique of the coercive elements of the
liberal abolitionist vision of contract, that takes up the rest of
the book.
Stanley first turns to critiques of contract articulated by northern
hirelings, making provocative and fruitful connections between
slavery, emancipation and industrial wage work. Stanley makes the
interesting point that "only in the United States did full-scale
industrial capitalism develop simultaneously with, and literally
alongside, the consolidation and overthrow of chattel slavery."(60)
In the wake of emancipation, American wage workers framed their
situation in terms of slavery and freedom, and argued that the
freedom to contract to sell one's labor on the market did not amount
to freedom in any meaningful sense at all. Hirelings rejected the
equation of the voluntary sale of labor with freedom, and asked
instead "whether the buying and selling of their labor as a market
commodity rendered them like or unlike chattel slaves." (62)
At the heart of the hireling critique was the notion that one's
labor could not be separated from one's self, and that to sell one's
labor on the market was in essence to sell one's self into a form of
slavery. The market, far from providing contract freedom as a
corrective for slavery, instead commodified labor to the point where
it sanctioned the creation of a new slave class. For many hirelings
"the inequality of power underlying the voluntary rituals of offer
and acceptance" belied the professed mutuality of labor and capital
and amounted instead to the forced sale of the self for a wage. (69)
Workers decried the "new slavery," (86) and raised again "the
question of buying, selling and owning human property." (96) The
link between wage slavery and chattel slavery is expertly drawn by
Stanley, and she makes a powerful case that Gilded Age labor issues
and emancipation were intimately, perhaps inseparably linked.
Stanley makes equally fascinating links between the issues raised by
emancipation, wage labor and marriage bonds. After the Civil War
feminists, who had long underscored the link between slavery and
common law coverture laws, "claimed that marriage belonged at the
very center of public debate over the outcome of slave
emancipation," and led the attack on "domestic slavery." (180)
Marriage, which law writers had been careful to distinguish from
other forms of contract relations, was attacked as another form of
legal subordination. Feminists more and more "invoked contract as a
model for equality in marriage," (184) demanding that a
relationship based on status be replaced by a contract relationship
based on self-ownership and voluntary exchange in which a wife could
buy and sell in the market, make contracts herself, and own
property. Marriage should thus mirror other contracts at law, a
claim quite different from hireling assertions that wage labor was
distinct from all other forms of contract. Feminists were of course
not wholly successful in dismantling the coverture regime, but
instead "brought to light a new set of contradictions" in which a
wife was left "without clear title to herself and her labor." (217)
Hirelings and married women drew a neat distinction between the
ability of the free market to either provide freedom or to take it
away. Married women demanded access to the market and to wages as
the benchmarks of freedom and self-ownership. Hirelings argued,
almost conversely, that the commodification of labor amounted to the
sale of the self. In both cases the free market was the foil for
competing conceptions of contract freedom.
But what about groups that operated totally outside the free market,
either by choosing not to contract their labor or by selling
something that was not recognized as a saleable commodity? If the
free market provided freedom, should everything be for sale?
Stanley poses and then explores these fascinating questions by
looking at the treatment of beggars and prostitutes in postbellum
America.
In the aftermath of slave emancipation, northern states enacted
harsh new vagrancy laws. These penalties against idleness obliged
former slaves and others to enter into wage contracts, "forcibly
inculcating the habits of free labor" and forming a "conjunction of
coercion and contract." (99) Ironically a nation recently purged of
chattel slavery established a new regime of forcible pauper labor.
The justification for forcing beggars to work was based on the
"natural law" of free market economies. (121) Beggars by refusing
to contract their labor upset the social order based on mutually
bargained exchange. Vagrancy laws "were represented as the
guarantee -- not the nullification -- of voluntary transactions."
(121)
Stanley is quick to point out that even the most devoted supporters
of these new laws recognized the contradiction that "a society
priding itself on having abolished slavery was forcibly extracting
labor from dependent persons." (133) The way out of this
contradiction was to frame vagrancy laws in terms of contract and
exchange -- and so they borrowed idioms from the marketplace to
define the treatment of beggars. In exchange for alms the beggar
provided labor -- this was the quid pro quo, and became a primary
justification for involuntary labor. Charity, formerly the "very
essence of a paternal relationship," was translated into free market
exchange. (135) In this way "the state enforced the sale of labor
-- through an involuntary exchange -- whenever beggars contrived to
avoid the natural sanctions of hunger and cold." (137) Stanley
thus uses the case of beggars to show how legal coercion and
enforced exchange could be framed and understood as part of the
operation of the free market.
Stanley also examines the relationship between free market contract
ideals and prostitution, observing that "in the eyes of the law the
streetwalker was the beggar's double; their common crime was roving
about and soliciting in public." (219) But in a culture that
celebrated market exchange, the sale of sex posed a contradiction
and was potentially "threatening [to] the legitimacy of contract as
a model of freedom" Prostitution seemed at once to be a form of
both voluntary and involuntary exchange and "the streetwalker was so
disturbing a presence precisely in her ambiguity -- a figure who
conspicuously blurred the difference between free and unfree
commodity relations, who could be seen as both the essence of
contract freedom and a vestige of slavery." (219)
This ambiguity was reflected in the controversy over the proposed
legalization and licensing of prostitution in the 1870s. Bills of
this type were introduced, Stanley writes, in almost all of the
nation's cities, including Philadelphia, the District of Columbia,
Chicago and San Francisco. The justification for these laws were
similar to vagrancy laws, namely to promote public health by keeping
roving persons off the street and to impose state control over free
market exchange. Despite support from doctors and police, these
bills were "defeated by anti-licensing coalitions led by former
abolitionists, feminists, and ministers who called themselves 'new
abolitionists.'" (251)
These 'new abolitionists' took up the language of the old
abolitionists, arguing that prostitution amounted to the
commodification of the self, and that state could not legitimize
this form of commerce any more than it could protect chattel
slavery. While wage laborers and married women had sought to make
similar arguments about the ways in which the commodification of
labor and the laws of coverture were themselves forms of slavery,
anti-licensing reformers alone were able to successfully equate
prostitution and slavery. Stanley closes the chapter with the
trenchant observation that for postbellum Americans concerned with
the operation of the market, it was "not labor but sex [that]
represented the human essence whose sale as a commodity transformed
its owners from free persons into slaves." (263)
Taken individually, Stanley's treatment of hirelings, married women,
freed slaves, beggars and prostitutes are each highly original,
surprising and informative. What seems at first blush a mostly
doctrinal analytical framing device -- the application and
contestation of ideas of contract -- becomes in this book a way of
making connections between a remarkable number of historical
sub-fields. Stanley's book is a rare find, a monograph that is at
once particular and rich in detail yet also genuinely synthetic.
Contract becomes a way of examining not only labor, but also
intellectual history, gender, race relations, home life, legal
culture, and political theory. This book will allow historians from
vastly different fields to talk with one another, and successfully
puts ideas of contract at the center of a striking number of
different historical questions and debates.
Taken as a whole this book forces us to reevaluate the notion that
the Gilded Age was an era marked by the embrace of laissez-faire
political economy and untrammeled individual freedom in the market.
Instead of unfettered acquisitive individuals, Stanley instead
traces the widespread use of state power to shape a particular
social order. The role and limits of a free market in the
postbellum market was, Stanley shows, not only up for grabs but
subject to violent debate framed explicitly in terms of slavery and
freedom. Stanley has discovered that emancipation set in motion a
debate over what constituted the illegitimate sale or
commodification of human beings. Chattel slavery? Wage labor?
Coverture? Prostitution? She reminds us that freedom defined as
free entry into the marketplace was but one definition of freedom
that competed with several others. By book's end Stanley has made
us aware, as historical actors in the 1870s and 1880s were all too
aware, of the contradiction of framing emancipation in terms of
market exchange. We are left with that contradiction still, or, as
Stanley closes her book, "there still exists the paradox that
slavery embodies the sale of human beings while freedom is imagined
as commodity exchange." (268)
Note
[1]. Morton Horwitz, "Freedom of Contract and Objective
Causation," in The Transformation of American Law (1992),
p.34.
Copyright (c) 2000 by H-Net, all rights reserved. This work
may be copied for non-profit educational use if proper credit
is given to the author and the list. For other permission,
please contact H-Net@h-net.msu.edu.